It is quite scandalous and perplexing to
undermine longstanding myths, but William Cavanaugh – Professor of Theology at
the University of St. Thomas - in his book The
Myth of Religious Violence compromises this myth in an extraordinary
thorough, clear and persuasive way. Cavanaugh meticulously crafted his argument
in explaining that in order to claim that religion is highly prone to violence
we have to make sure that such term as religion can be clearly identified and
explained. He presents an argument that the term religion didn't naturally
occur, but was created by political thinkers, historians and philosophers
during 16-17th centuries for legitimizing state formation and
excluding Church from any social power. Further, the author argues that in most
of the phenomenon of so-called 'religious violence' it is extremely hard to
make a sharp distinction between its religious or secular causes. Thus, this
myth is irrelevant in understanding violence committed by different people that
may claim their violence to be done in the name of God or for some other
religious purposes. To make the argument of the myth of 'religious violence'
multidimensional, I will take into consideration Ephraim Radner's book A Brutal Unity which serves as a
counter-argument to Cavanaugh's book. While Cavanaugh provides well-thought and
thorough research on Thirty Years Wars of Religion, Radner argues that
Cavanaugh misinterprets relations between Church and Liberal state and their
mutual benefits from each other’s existence. Moreover, Radner insists that
because of this misinterpretation Cavanaugh fails to explain or justify modern
examples of 'religious violence' such as Rwandan genocide. Finally, by writing The Myth of Religious Violence, in
Radners strong opinion, Cavanaugh not just creates an excuse for Christian
violence, but actually encourages future violence as well. In this essay I will
provide a critical analysis of William Cavanaugh's book The Myth of Religious Violence as well as present Radner's
opposition on the issue of the myth of 'religious violence' that is described
in A Brutal Unity and finally I will
prove that it is absolutely essential to consider and review all possible
religious as well as secular influences of violent behavior of any individuals
or groups of individuals in order to comprehend a problem of world's violence
in its entirety.
At the beginning of
his argument William Cavanaugh emphasizes the importance of understanding the
term religion especially its meaning, context and different ways how it can be
used and applied in our lives if we want to speak about the myth of 'religious
violence'. Cavanaugh insists that many modern theorists like Nicholas of Cusa,
Marsilio Ficino, Thomas Hobbes, and John Locke fail to comprehend and accept
the myth of 'religious violence' because they don't succeed to understand the
concept of religion as a social construct rather than a timeless unchanging
phenomenon that is transhistorical and transcultural (Lloyd). This means that
religion always meant the same thing and encompassed the same qualities through
different historical eras and cultural settings. He argues that what considered
as secular or religious in any given moment largely depends on underlying
societal power arrangements. Further, Cavanaugh claims that these thinkers
treat religion as something essentially distinct from secular and something that
is not overlapping with politics, economics or other social structures. As the
result, 'religion' has strong inclination for violence, thus 'secular' power
has to tame 'religion.' To prove these thinkers wrong, Cavanaugh traces back to
an ancient Rome and the Latin word “religio” from which the word religion
originated, but which carries a different meaning from modern religion. “There
was a time when religion, as modern people use the term, was not,” claims
Cavanaugh, because religio was like a devotion to anything from God, to family,
to emperor, to hobbies (Cavanaugh 81). Religio was not a separate practice of
social life, but was fully integrated in everything else that people did and
thought. Thus, it is hard to blame early Christianity for their religious
violence, because there was no such thing as religion that they clearly
identified and practiced. In our present days the only situation when we still
use religion in the meaning of old religio
is when we say that were are “doing something religiously”.
There is no such clear
distinction on what religion is and what it is not, Cavanaugh claims, and
different people have different ways of trying to define religion. In
substantivist view of religion the content matters the most and they heavily refer
to ideas such as belief in God, transcendence, or the sacred. This approach is
known to be too exclusive because it restricts non-theistic Asian beliefs like
Buddhism, but on the criterion of transcendence it has to include nationalism
as a religion. Further, functonalist perspective disregards the content of
religion and is more concerned on how religion works and what people actually
practice. By doing so, functionalism includes too many things like civil
religion, political religion, or idol adoration. Cavanaugh criticizes both of
these approaches because they “tend to be essentialist approaches that regard
religion as a thing out there in the world, a basic, transhistorical, and
transcultural component of human social life identifiable by its content or
function” (Cavanaugh 58). The constructivist explanation of religion tends to
represent Cavanaugh's view the best because it looks at historical
circumstances and specific purposes under which nationalism, Confucianism,
Islam, etc., are considered religions. Religion is “a constructed category, not
a neutral descriptor of a reality that is simply out there in the world”
(Cavanaugh 58). Constructivists discovered that the term religion as we know it
today was developed by Western thinkers and was often used by colonizers to
marginalize and manipulate native populations to their advantage. In order to
concur a territory westerns would prove that practice of faith or devotion of
native population is irrational; thus, it had to be dismissed from public use
and be kept for private use only. By doing so they were able to divide,
embarrass, downgrade and rule these native people. Religion of Hinduism, as we
know it today, was inseparable from Indian's every day social and political
life, but English colonizers extracted it out and forced Indians to keep it
private. Islam is still inseparable from any other secular parts of people's
lives; therefore, Western people think that Muslim world is irrational,
barbaric and backward and that it should be tamed, educated, and reformatted.
Very often when
people try to prove the existence and severity of religious violence they cite
a Thirty years War of religion in sixteen and seventeen century Europe. In the
light of great historical thinkers these wars were heavily influenced by
religious differences between Catholics and Protestants that couldn't agree on
each other’s dogmatic differences. This proved that religion is too passionate
and irrational; thus, it fails to maintain peace and order in the society
(Lloyd). As a solution to these bloody killings a liberal nation state occurred
as a more rational, peaceful and ultimate object of loyalty. The state was able
to tame religion from its own irrationality and stop the war by forcing church
to leave the front public stage into the back private room, that allowed
Catholics and protestant to peacefully live with their differences (Philpott).
Even though this theory sounds clear and persuasive, William Cavanaugh
radically reinterprets the Thirty years War of religious violence and challenges
four major problems of the standard liberal chronicle. He undermines view that
combatants that fought with each other did so because of religious differences;
the primary cause of the war was religion, not political, economic, or societal
differences; religious causes were absolutely separable from secular cause; and
finally the rise of modern state was a solution to the war. First, Cavanugh provides multiple occasions
when members of different churches collaborated together, while members of the
same church viciously were killing each other. Also, the entire second half of
the war was fought by Catholic France and Catholic Habsburg and very often
mercenaries fought for a higher bidder regardless of their religious
commitments. Second, it is very difficult if not impossible to distinguish
relative religious as opposed to political, economic or other social causes of
this war, because it is almost to the end of the war when these terms were
purposefully developed and clearly identified. Cavanaugh asserts that the
narrative of devout Christians fanatically killing each other for religious
differences is a “myth [that] is at best a distorted and one-dimensional
narrative; at worst, it eliminates so many of the relevant political, economic,
and social factors as to be rendered false” (Cavanaugh 155). Third, as
mentioned earlier religion was so intertwined with the rest of people's social
life it is almost impossible to distinguish politics from religion, religion
from economics and your “attempt to assign the cause of the wars in question to
religion – as opposed to politics or other secular causes – will get bogged
down in hopeless anachronism” (Cavanaugh 160).
Fourth myth that Cavanaugh compromises is that the formation of the
state was eventual solution to the problem or religious wars; while in reality
it was one of the primary causes. The
“transfer of power from church to the state appears not so much as a solution
to the wars in question, but as a cause of those wars. The so-called wars of
religion appear as wars fought by state-building elites for the purpose of
consolidating their power over the church and other rivals”(Cavanaugh 162).
Cavanaugh explains that by marginalizing religion from the public sphere,
nation-state was able to transfer all of the power from church to the state.
That’s why it is more relevant, in Cavanugh's opinion, to talk about wars of
early modern European state formation.
In order for the state
to appropriate power of the Church it had to remove it from any spheres of its
influence. Therefore, religion was presented as too passionate and irrational
in its decision-making process and it had to be substituted by more rational,
modest, liberal state. There were several problems with this assumption since
the liberal state got solidified and arrived only a century after these wars
ended (Philpott). That means that after religion got suppressed from the power
of the society, people began killing for god-like queens and kings and the
so-called migration of the Holly came to place. In his interview with Donald
A.Yerxa William Cavanaugh explains, “Nationalism ensured that the loyalties
previously attached to God and Church were transferred to the new
nation-state.” Since the religion became a private practice and something that
people didn't speak about in public, it became unheard off to die for Jesus or
any other religious beliefs (Lloyd). On the other hand, it was more reasonable
to die for your country, freedom, flag and oil. Westerns began to think that we
overcame irrational killing for religion, but the truth is that we just began
killing for the state with the same if not even stronger devotion and passion.
Ephraim Radner in his
book A Brutal Unity raises multiple
objections to William Cavanaugh's argument of our delusion in understanding the
religious violence. In his opinion Cavanaugh fails to understand “ 'religion'
with respect to violence, a significance that itself religious,” as the result
he fails to understand modern versions for religious violence like case of
Rwandan genocide and finally, he undermines positive relations between Church
and State, which to the degree is more beneficial for the Church itself.
Radner's first argument to Cavanaugh is his misleading attempt to define the
modern term 'religion' and he suggests that its better to look at the religion
“in terms of practices rather than concepts” because dogma may say one thing
but in practice do something different, because people are sinners in their
nature (Radner 21). Radner argues that synonymous words of our modern western
understanding of religion existed in pre-modern era such as sectum, fides and
etc. These terms identified different ways of idolatry of different Gods or
transcendent, which are very similar to our understanding of modern religion
(Resch). Further, there is a major difficulty with Cavanaugh's argument because
“it fails to take seriously the actual attitudes of participants in what is
called ‘religious violence’ ” (Radner 25).
Anybody who claims that they committed an act of their violence in the
name of God is committing religious violence, explains Radner. Even if there is
an underlying secular factor in this violence, the fact that the person claims
his act as a religious makes it religious automatically. This claim seems very
troubling and requires more explanation, especially in the modern acts of
so-called religious violence. While affected by different secular influences
such as economics and politics, many people become desperate and with their
materialistic goals and reasons in mind they commit violence. This violence,
further, is claimed to be religious because its more poetic to an extent to
fight in the name of God and for the purpose that is bigger than yourself, when
in reality you fight for the basic human injustice (Long).
Second, Radner claims
that Cavanaugh and other like thinkers “unjustifiably absolve Christians from
their share in the violence of the liberal state” (Radner 22). By justifying
the creation of the nation-state as primary cause and not a solution, Church
and its divisiveness that caused the violence ends up being innocent in this
war. However, it seems that Ephraim Radner misinterprets the argument of
William Cavanaugh, because in The Myth of
Religious Violence he neither rejects nor excuses religious violence during
16-17th centuries, nor does he doubt that some religious ideas and
practices did promote violence under certain conditions. What Cavanaugh
actually challenged in his book is that there were something distinguishably
clear that could have been called religion that people were fighting for.
Further, Radner explains that “the Church need[ed] the liberal state as much as
the liberal state need[ed] the church, because the nations as we know them
arose from the inability of Christians to refrain from mutual murder” (Radner 28).
Radner rejects Cavanaugh's idea that the formation of the state actually
triggered the war; instead it came as the only possible solution to stop the
violence by taking power of the church away and look at the world with more
pragmatic point of view. Radner continuing to explain that the creation of the
liberal state was actually beneficial for the Church in light of the fact that
because of long-lasting bloody war, Christian Church began to loose its
popularity and even further its holiness (W. Klink A). Therefore, the liberal
state did a big favor to the Church by taming its violence and taking away its
power and maybe “not so much as to protect it from itself (although this could be said in some cases)
as to provide a framework for self-accountability” (Radner 22).
Radner's last and
biggest argument is Cavanugh's failure to understand the modern examples of
religious violence on the example of Rwandan Genocide. Since Christianity was
the predominant religion in the Rwanda and it was heavily involved and even in
charge in education, medical field and other social aspects of every day life,
it is absolutely essential to recognize religious involvement in the genocide
and admit its responsibility. He begins by explaining that “Cavanaugh misses
out on paying attention on Christianity’s divisive nature at birth” which means
that already existed division and rivalry of Hutu and Tutsi was not criticized
by the church, but even supported (Radner 26). Cavanaugh's argument to that
would be that even though the division existed already in the Christianity as
well as in Rwanda, it is impossible to claim that religion stimulated
previously existed socio-political conflict. Moreover, taking into
consideration detailed analysis of Longman, that Radner cites in his book, will
only support Cavanaugh's argument that there we many others significant factors
that influenced the genocide such as “the progressive colonial and
national-building aspects of ethnic differentiation, social distinction,
separatist policy, organized political assault, and finally violence. Into
these dynamics, the churches were swept, along with every other institution”
(Radner 30). This reassures even more Cavanaugh's view that what is 'religious'
and what is 'secular' is impossible to clearly differentiate. Radner's
response/criticism is that “Christians killed each other, [...], because of the
kind of Christianity they had
embraced – a message of 'obedience, division, and power' - whose dynamics
rendered them 'unable or unwilling to restrain genocide.' To this degree their
faith was wholly complicit in murder” (Radner 31).
Further, Radner raises
the questions that “given that Christians did the killing and did so surrounded
by their lived Christian symbols and spatial forms and led often by their Christian
pastors, in some cases taking Mass quite self-consciously before going out to
kill, how are we to understand the nature of their faith?” (Radner 31). By
documenting how Christians were unable to prevent violence, Radner is now
taking step back and not suggesting that religious division causes violence, as
he claimed earlier, as much as it coheres with it, which is to say, Christian
division is not the exclusive inflamer of violence, but it is a central one
(Resch). At this point it is unclear which position represents Radner's view on
Rwandan genocide better, either that Christians primarily triggered the
violence or failed to prevent it. It is very important to understand that under
which historical and cultural circumstances did this genocide occur. While Christianity
was brought to Rwandans by the English colonizers, their ethnic differences
existed way before that and were in-rooted in their cultures and perception of
each other. At this point Radner
presents a third approach to the problem where he states that “the problem is
that Christian violence in itself
bears a range of terrible consequences, obscuring God's truth, and hence
religious violence has a horrendous character peculiar to itself” (Radner 28).
Here he admits that not all Christians are devout believers and under certain
social pressures some of them easily give up their beliefs. This is a result of
Church's inability to create and nourish strong enough faiths in people's souls
that will be able to serve as the core belief system to resist any opposing
pressures (Long). This argument seems to be one of the most relevant and
valuable in comparison to other views that he doesn't stick to for a very long
time. If look at people as something constructed by both secular and religious
aspects, it seems that religion has to be able to provide people at least with
strong sets of moral beliefs and social standards that they are ready to stand
for, but as William Cavanaugh argues, at various historical periods and
different cultural settings religion takes different shapes and places in
people's life and there is no such thing as a universal religion that everybody
practice the same.
The final argument of
Ephraim Radner is religious proneness to demonization of others, where “[d]emonization is a religious concept, bound not only to particular Christian
categories, […], but also to the process of scriptural and theological
translation” (Radner 35). He examines that Christians historically used
Biblical images of Satan and sinners to apply to others in order to raise
support for their unjustified violence. Cavanaugh argues with this notion that
religion intensifies political conflicts into unsolvable cosmic wars against
'satanic' others because this view ignores how secular wars and political
reasoning is able to use the same tendencies but with greater intensiveness.
William Cavanaugh without a moment of hesitation uses a provocative example,
where he insists that there is no “warrant for supposing that the commitment of
a US Marine – semper fidelis – is any
less “intense” than that of a Hamas militant, as if such a thing could be
measured” (Cavanaugh 32).
To the end of this
essay I want to clarify that in Radner's critique of Cavanaugh he misses out a
lot of points by looking only at the case of Christianity and its divisiveness
instead of the wide spectrum of different religions, if this term makes any
sense at all now, and secular devotions. By doing so Radner wanted to
concentrate on specific subject and make it easier to make a convincing argument
to Cavanaugh, but instead he failed to understand the bigger argument that
Cavanaugh succeeded to make. Moreover, even if Radner’s view about Christian
divisiveness as well as Castelios explanation of different sectums are right,
than the question of why Catholics and Protestants didn't begin to kill each
other earlier remains unanswered. Radner is mislead by his eager to make a
strong counter-argument to Cavanaugh, that he fails to see that Cavanaugh never
tries to create an excuse for Christianity or any other religions for their
violence, and he very clearly and on multiple occasions states that religion
can and was violent, but we can't be absolutist and, accept this as the only
cause for this violence. As Cavanaugh proved already that you can not talk about
these wars in terms of the root divisiveness of Christianity, because there
were multiple occasions where people with the same religious views were killing
each other and people with different religious views were cooperating. In the example
of Rwandan genocide there were many Hutus helping Tutsis, while some Tutsis
were killing their own kind in order to save their political standings or
lives. Radner, using Longman's theory, has only one valuable, in my opinion,
point that the church failed to prevent the violence. It seems that the strong
religious views and beliefs should be at the core of peoples life and life
views, thus when the violence occurs they should be able to resist this
violence. However, we have to realize that in life people will most likely
change, or give up their religious views when their entire existence comes
under question. The main idea of this essay is to illustrate that in order to
fully understand any existing world problem you have to look into the
complexity of causes and problems as they usually come in the entire package,
instead of picking one possible cause and concentrate on it, because by looking
only for one excuse is the easy way out of the problem of answering complex
questions.
Works Cited:
Cavanaugh, William T. "If You Render Unto God What Is God's,
What Is Left for Caesar?" The Review of Politics 71.4
(2009): 607-19. JSTOR. Web. 10 Mar. 2014.
<http://www.jstor.org/stable/25655866>.
Cavanaugh, William T. The
Myth of Religious Violence:Secular Ideology and the Roots of Modern Conflict.
New York And Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009. ix-285. Print.
Lloyd, Vincent.
"Cavanaugh, William T. The Myth of Religious Violence:Secular Ideology and
the Roots of Modern Conflict."Theory, Culture & Society 28.5
(2011): 144-54. SAGE Journals. Web. 10 Mar. 2014.
<http://tcs.sagepub.com.libproxy.usc.edu/content/28/5/144>.
Long, Stephen D. "A
Brutal Unity: The Spiritual Politics of the Christian Church by Ephraim
Radner." Modern Theology 30.1 (2014): 166-68. Web. 10
Mar. 2014. <http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/moth.12085>.
Philpott, Daniel. "The Religious Roots of
Modern International Relations." World
Politics 52.2 (2000): 206-45. JSTOR. Web. 10 Mar. 2014.
<http://www.jstor.org/stable/25054109>.
Radner, Ephraim. A Brutal Unity: The Spiritual Politics of the Christian Church.
Texas: Baylor University Press, 2012. Print.
Resch, Dustin. "A Brutal Unity: The
Spiritual Politics of the Christian Church." Anglican Theological
Review 95.3 (2013): 566-67. ProQuest. Web. 10 Mar. 2014.
<http://libproxy.usc.edu/login?url=http://search.proquest.com.libproxy.usc.edu/docview/1420130380?accountid=14749>.
W, Klink A. "A
brutal unity: the spiritual politics of the Christian church." Choice 50.12
(2013): 2248-49. ProQuest. Web. 10 Mar. 2014.
<http://libproxy.usc.edu/login?url=http://search.proquest.com.libproxy.usc.edu/docview/1428955342?accountid=14749>.
I agree with you on the point that we cannot attribute only one cause to such complex issues as genocides, wars, and other types of violence. I also agree with you in that other types of dogmatic thinking, like nationalism, can be just as harmful as religion when it comes to riling up people's violent tendencies. However, I do think it is important to clarify in your essay that it is not a "myth" that religions often cause and perpetuate violence. To say that this is a myth implies that it misrepresents the truth, when I think most people, including yourself, admit that religions can and have spurred violence in the past. Furthermore, what has always disturbed me about organized religion has been the fact that people accept its teachings with such ease and with such little question, even though religions are products of human beings just like ourselves who did not know everything and were not perfect. While there are certainly many secular beliefs that inspire the same type of ignorance, it is important to recognize how religions have historically stripped people of the ability to think for themselves, and we should always question the place of such beliefs in our society.
ReplyDelete